Category Archives: Goodness

God: Trinity and Unity

God is a trinity on the 2nd level, insofar as each person of the Trinity has His own unique separate and distinct intellect, will, and power.

God is a unity for 3 reasons. First, the 3 levels in God are united into a single "thing."

Second, each person's intellect is an aspect of the intellect of God. The same is true for the wills and powers of the persons.

In particular, for God, His love of concupiscence, love of self, and love of friendship are numerically identical to each other. God loves Himself as a "consumer good" or object of contemplation; He loves His own self, such that the lover, the beloved, and the love (understood as everything God approves of and enjoys about Himself) are God Himself; and God manifests His love for the other through the relations of the Trinity.

Thus, the Father and the Son love each other through the Holy Spirit. But the effects of love are, as per St. Thomas, union, mutual indwelling, ecstasy, and zeal: "when a man loves another with the love of friendship, he wills good to him, just as he wills good to himself: wherefore he apprehends him as his other self, in so far, to wit, as he wills good to him as to himself. Hence a friend is called a man's 'other self'..., and Augustine says..., 'Well did one say to his friend: Thou half of my soul.'" (ST, II-I, 28) The Father and Son then indwell in each other perfectly and wholeheartedly together with the Holy Spirit, making them one. Each person is "another self" to the other two persons.

This relation may be also approached as follows: the lover unites with the beloved, is completed through this union, and rests in peace therefrom. The divine mind (Father) that thinks and through one comprehensive thought (Holy Spirit) understands itself (Son), while maintaining an identity of these three as simple pure act achieves precisely this sort of completeness and as its consequence, beatitude or happiness.

Third, the acts of the divine intellect, will, and power are in fact self-same single act.

See also:

Mea Culpa on the Trinity,
One God,
Trinity: Ad Intra and Ad Extra.

First Cause As Last End

St. Thomas aims to prove that there is such a thing as "last end" for humans. He correctly identifies it as happiness. Further, he believes that it is specifically "the sole contemplation of God seen in His essence" that grants perfect pleasure. It's what puts the mind at ease and rest, what satisfies all desire: the vision and secure possession of all truth, even if God remains infinite and beyond full comprehension for any finite creature. Thus, "if man's happiness is an operation, it must needs be man's highest operation. Now man's highest operation is that of his highest power in respect of its highest object: and his highest power is the intellect, whose highest object is the Divine Good, which is the object, not of the practical but of the speculative intellect. ... Therefore the last and perfect happiness, which we await in the life to come, consists entirely in contemplation." (ST, II-I, 3, 5)

I have two objections to this.

First is that there is no such thing as "perfect happiness" even in contemplation. The object of vision, God, obviously cannot improve, but the understanding of a blessed soul or angel can, with time. There has to be continuous learning of new things, new insights, including even by the angels. The idea of a permanent changeless operation is repugnant to the nature of all rational creatures as potentially infinite.

Second is that the human body is not a disposable consumer good, as though "the very body is for the soul, as matter for its form, and the instruments for the man that puts them into motion, that by their means he may do his work." (II-I, 2, 5) The body is not like a shovel or granola bar but an essential aspect of humanity; and this is precisely how we differ from the angels. The embodied pleasures for humans in paradise will be equal in intensity and fun to the disembodied pleasure of contemplating God in heaven.

For example, St. Thomas is wrong in thinking that the "the fellowship of friends" is not necessary for happiness: "Perfection of charity is essential to happiness, as to the love of God, but not as to the love of our neighbor. Wherefore if there were but one soul enjoying God, it would be happy, though having no neighbor to love." (II-I, 4, 8, reply 3) He seems to contradict himself in (I, 106): even regarding contemplation, he argues that superior angels enlighten inferior ones in the celestial hierarchy and always will. Much more then do angels and greater saints enlighten the lesser souls in the state of glory.

Even if contemplation of God is a somewhat solitary activity, in paradise a solitary human would be rather miserable. Humans are highly social creatures, complementing each other in a vast variety of ways. To deprive us from the communion of saints is to harm us immensely and unjustly. Thus, Jesus' words to the crucified thief were not, "Today you will be with the Father in heaven," but "Today you will be with me in paradise." (Lk 23:43) It seems therefore that in heaven the Holy Spirit will unite each man with the Father; and in paradise, He will unite us with each other and with the Son.

The whole reason for the enormous sacrifices God has made through the fall of angels and men and the death of His Son and massive human suffering on earth has been to unite the universe into a one thing through different types of love or charity. To turn around and blithely proclaim that the communion between humans, between men and nature, and so forth, as described earlier, is all of a sudden actually irrelevant or at most an afterthought is a major mistake. We can excuse St. Thomas only because in his times, neither economic science nor laissez-faire capitalism existed, and the idea of everlasting progress in man's active life was completely unknown and unentertained.

St. Thomas' proof that one's contemplative life is perfected by the vision of God in heaven is adequate: all intellectual wonder is satisfied by beholding the source and archetype of all things. That in addition to heaven, there is also paradise in which one's active life is perfected requires a different proof. Or rather, the idea of paradise can be developed a priori, but whether paradise actually exists is an empirical problem which can be resolved by considering the Incarnation of the Son. We know that the Incarnation occurred, that Jesus is God, that He was born so that His love for us could be tested by our ultimate injustice toward Him personally -- by following the evidence. Since we know that Jesus united human nature, soul and body both, to the divinity, we can deduce that the happiness in the embodied active life can be one of our rewards in the hereafter.

The passage, "What eye has not seen, and ear has not heard, and what has not entered the human heart, what God has prepared for those who love him," (1 Cor 2:9) is best interpreted as the promise of future enjoyments in paradise, since, contrary to it, we do know exactly what God has prepared for man's contemplation in heaven, and that is Himself.

Now we must make a distinction between our ability to conceive what will make a man happy and whether this happiness is reachable. Now regarding the contemplative life, St. Thomas argues in (I, 12, 4) that no created intellect by its natural powers can see the divine essence. And regarding the active life, reason tells us that humans not only fail to enjoy everlasting improvement and perpetual novel pleasures in paradise, but that they fail to secure life itself, since everyone dies including often in terrible pain. Therefore, that both kinds of happiness are attainable by man is a deliverance not of reason but of faith.

And with that, we have it that union with God is our last end for our both contemplative and active lives.

Re: Dillahunty Objects to the Arguments from Contingency

A speech by Matt Dillahunty was linked to for my edification from an atheist website on which I presented my arguments for the existence of God from "contingency."

At the beginning, Matt distinguishes between two kinds of contingency: "causal" and "sustaining." P may be dependent on Q for its coming to exist, but also for its continuing to exist. Thus, he argues that it is possible that some X caused or created the contingent universe and then disappeared. My own arguments are untouched by this distinction, because they all ask what ultimately sustains contingent things in being, such as the unions of (1) potency and existence; (2) act and existence; (3) potency and act.

There are three kinds of necessity relevant to this problem. The first type of necessity I call "imperishability." An object is necessary in this sense if, once it exists, it will never stop existing (and perhaps always has existed). Yet such an object is still contingent, because there will always be possible (though non-actual) ways to destroy it. There is no such thing as an ordinary indestructible object, because we can always postulate an irresistible force in some possible world that will smash it into smithereens. The proof begins with noting the perishability of numerous things and continues that there must be at least one thing that is imperishable or necessary in the first sense.

Matt appears to wonder what we can point to that is imperishable. I list three things: matter, in accordance with the law of conservation of matter and energy; certain forms, such as a stable elementary particle of some sort perhaps that is sure to exist forever; and the universe as a whole. Different arguments follow from each of these.

The second sense of necessity is illustrated by an X in which it's not the case that its essence and its existence are united by yet a third thing or force or what have you, but such that its essence and existence are numerically identical to each other, self-same. St. Thomas pronounces this astounding thing in particular to be "what all men call God." Imperishable matter and forms are such merely in this actual world; X is imperishable in all possible worlds. Matter and these imperishable objects are necessary in the first sense but not in the second sense. This time, it is not possible even logically to separate X's nature from its existence, because they are one and the same thing. However, the universe as a whole might indeed be necessary in the second sense, too, as far as we are concerned, and as Matt proposes. Must we then allow that the "cosmos" might be "God"?

Now let us not underestimate our achievement so far. We've already established that there must be some thing that is extremely and fantastically different from ordinary matter and objects in the fact that its essence is its own existence. We may stop here and call this "God." Matt objects to calling it God, because it may be the "cosmos as a whole," whatever it is, that may feature this very property. And I agree that there are further insights to be gained by following the argument to its final stage.

Note that even if it is possible for the cosmos to be necessary in the second sense, the cosmos cannot cause the necessity (in the first sense) of matter and imperishable forms. This is because all those are part of the cosmos, and the whole cannot give existence to its parts; rather the reverse. Whatever X is keeping things in perpetual existence must be distinct from the cosmos, even if both X and the cosmos are necessary in the second sense.

The third and last sense of necessity for us is modal logical necessity. In the X under our investigation, it has been revealed, there is a perfect (i.e., numerical) union of being and essence; but if the "cosmos," understood as everything that there is, consists in nothing but "being," then there may be possible worlds in which X does not exist at all. If God exists, then He is absolutely imperishable or necessary in the second sense. But He has not yet been demonstrated to be necessary in the third sense, as is evident from the ease with which His non-existence can be contemplated by the mind. Matt refuses to engage the question "Why is there something rather than nothing?" apparently considering it nonsensical, but I urge him to change his mind. It is a perfectly reasonable query.

And as I therefore argue, the answer to it is that X is not really a "thing" at all; it is rather the Creator of things. Insofar as we (hopefully) are willing to consider the cosmos to be a good thing, its Creator would be the quintessence of goodness itself. This goodness is beyond being. For the sake of illustration only, and we are now going beyond our argument, the Father-Son-Holy Spirit would be perfectly and infinitely happy on the "2nd, spiritual" level. God on His ultimate and unique 3rd level of goodness does not seek happiness at all; but this goodness overflows and diffuses itself into things-that-seek-happiness, such as human beings. Even the Trinity is comparatively a mere attachment to God's essential goodness. As such, X-as-goodness transcends possible worlds and exists in all of them. Our X is now necessary in the fullest and most spectacular sense of this word.

Regarding the name of God, "goodness," I have a counter-argument. Imagine a world W of intelligent crystals who reproduce against their will, who live a long time, and who are always in agonizing pain. They long to die. Eventually, they develop the technology to commit suicide and actually all, as one, kill themselves. It is doubtful that even if the crystals reasoned their way to God's existence, they would concede His goodness. At the very least, W would clearly be incompetently and probably maliciously made. I submit that given the knowledge of God we've obtained in the course of this argument, it is more likely that W is an impossible world. It is conceivable, but there is a difference between what is conceivable and what is possible. W is only apparently possible and in fact not; hence, we are barred from using this example to argue against God's goodness.

Again, it is true that humans have on many occasions created a hell on earth, but very rarely to such an extent as to, through their crimes, cause their fellows to want to die.

Matt complains that the proofs under consideration do not supply us with the full understanding of God; they give us only a slice of God. Well, that is enough for these proofs. There are other proofs that reveal other aspects of the divine nature.

My methodology is that at the beginning of any systematic unveiling of the nature of "God," I deliberately forget so much as the common meaning of the term "God." I assume nothing. The most I allow myself is a question, "What is this God that other people occasionally mention in their speech?" Matt may object that I am still conditioned by my "culture" to use the word "God." True, but I do so only because I want to be understood rather than stew in my own solipsistic juices. Matt can hardly condemn a desire so innocent.

In sum, the argument from contingency succeeds at establishing a number of attributes of God; and moreover the use of the word "God" should cause the skeptic no offense, especially upon demonstration of how greatly God differs from creatures.

Arguments for God’s Existence from Contingency

St. Thomas begins his Third Way by saying that "we find in nature things that are possible to be and not to be, since they are found to be generated, and to corrupt, and consequently, they are possible to be and not to be." (ST, I, 2, 3)

Now if the universe began, then "at some point," to use this phrase loosely, there was nothing. If, on the other hand, the universe never began, then things in it must have existed forever, for an actual infinity of, say, years. (This isn't 100% intelligible in its own right, but let's suppose this for the sake of argument.) But if it is possible for an existing thing not to be, then the probability of its corrupting within some finite span of time is non-zero. But in infinite time, all probable events will occur, and an infinite number of times, too. Hence he goes on that "if everything is possible not to be, then at one time there could have been nothing in existence." Either way, this is a problem, because "if at one time nothing was in existence, it would have been impossible for anything to have begun to exist; and thus even now nothing would be in existence -- which is absurd."

St. Thomas correctly concludes that "not all beings are merely possible, but there must exist something the existence of which is necessary." Here is where he and I part ways.

First, let's purge the argument of ambiguity: "necessary" here does not mean modal logical necessity but simply "imperishable." An imperishable thing is such that, once it exists, it will always exist and by extension, perhaps it always has existed.

Second, let's enumerate some of those imperishable things. They are:

  1. Matter, and as its limiting variant, prime or formless matter, ghostly pure potentiality; something which can become anything. Matter can change from one form to another and even to energy, but according to the law of conservation, it cannot die.

    We can understand prime matter as what remains if we take any real object and strip away all its distinctive characteristics. Prime matter has no essence; but neither is it non-existence. To say that prime matter exists is to say that it is potentially, given the appropriate agent, all possible things, but no actual thing.

  2. Certain forms may well be imperishable. For example, perhaps electrons can never corrupt. (Technically, they, too, can collide with positrons and be annihilated, but it may well be that some actual things are imperishable.)

    Note that an electron is considered to be an elementary particle, but it has a definite form; it is not a fully inert and property-less point of prime matter. An electron behaves in highly precise and unique ways. It knows what it is full well.

  3. The universe as a whole seems to be imperishable. For example, there are no "predators" outside it that may kill it. The universe does not seem to have the potential for disappearing. It is not beyond the pale to suggest that it will exist forever.

    There are a couple of other possibilities that we can list.

  4. Perhaps a certain object may change forms on a regular basis: say, one year on March 12, A changes into B, and then next year on June 5, B changes back into A, and so on forever. However, we can reduce this situation to one object P whose single essence includes in its definition the potential for all such changes.

    Thus, liquid water turns into snow and ice in winter, melts in spring, and evaporates into gas in summer. But it's still water.

    Finally, perhaps forms may change into novel and never-before-seen forms forever: A-∞ → ... → A-1 → A0 → A1 → ... → A.

    But we don't seem to have such forms in our universe.

Third, let's see what the first 3 things tell us, if anything, about God. St. Thomas outlines the procedure by concluding: "Every necessary thing either has its necessity caused by another, or not. Now it is impossible to go on to infinity in necessary things which have their necessity caused by another... Therefore we cannot but postulate the existence of some being having of itself its own necessity, and not receiving it from another, but rather causing in others their necessity. This all men speak of as God."

1. Prime matter makes all possible things potential. But what is possible and what is potential are two separate and distinct things that are united within prime matter. For example, it is easy for us to contemplate possible worlds and possible things. The fat man in the doorway has a partially specified essence, but he does not exist in reality. I form an idea of a lamp by abstracting the "essence" of the lamp from the singular object on my desk. This idea exists in the understanding as an ideal abstractum, but it may or may not exist really. Possibilities on their own are causally inefficacious and have no potential to exist.

Even prime matter, and therefore the union in it of the possible with the potential, then is contingent. It must be explained which means be reduced to a cause. Let a certain X cause prime matter. What can we assert about this X? Well, it causes possible things to become potential. If these are separated, then we are back to prime matter which cannot be a cause of itself. The inevitable conclusion is that in X, possibilities and potentialities are numerically identical with each other, self-same. They are not 2 separate things that need to be united by a 3rd object (as, e.g., (1) a man is united with (2) his life by (3) his self-love), because they are literally one and the same thing. That is what we mean by God: a thing in which everything possible is also potential, i.e., can be actualized. But that means that God possesses absolute and unlimited creative power.

This seems like an important first discovery in our investigation.

I am not proposing that the existence of prime matter entails the existence of the omnipotent shaper of prime matter directly. Oil has existed under the ground for far longer than there have been humans and for longer than humans have known how to transform oil into gasoline. At first glance, there may be formless matter with no one to use it. It is superficially conceivable that there is prime matter without God. But only because of the initial weakness of the human intellect. Such a thing is not possible.

It may be objected that God may have the power to create prime matter but lack any power to create anything further out of prime matter. God can make everything makeable but not necessarily makeable by Himself later on. Moreover, prime matter seems exceedingly simple. Perhaps it is easy for God to create it but impossible to create anything else with its assistance. In reply, I say that prime matter is simple actually but is infinitely complex potentially, since absolutely everything, from ladybugs to angels, can be fashioned out of it. Prime matter is inseparable from the art of using it. There is no way that a weak God could make a substance as infinitely versatile and wondrous as prime matter, unless His power to make reached everything which prime matter's power to be made also reaches. Hence God is ad extra omnipotent.

NB: Prime matter is a technical term for pure potentiality. Hence, even immaterial souls, including human and angelic, can be made out of it, too. There is no need to add "prime spirit."

2. This one is easier to unravel. An imperishable thing may nevertheless be contingent. That this is so can be established by the ease with which I can abstract the electron's essence from the singular thing. I can say that while I am contemplating this essence in my mind, the electron is an ideal abstractum; when instantiated, it becomes real. The essence of the election is a possible thing, and it may or may not be actual.

In the previous argument we considered the union of potentiality (matter) with existence. Now we proceed to the union of actuality (form) with existence.

This union must be effected through some "glue" that unites essence and existence which is not identical with either but is something super-added to both. The glue is probably some form of divine love which is the preeminent unitive force. Again then, even if the electron is imperishable, it is contingent, and the glue must be caused by something else.

But of course the cause must be a really existing object X, also, since ideal abstracta are causally inefficacious. (Nor is the electron's existence a proper accident of the nature of the electron, as the capacity to laugh is a proper accident of humanity. Nor, furthermore, can a thing cause its own existence.) Which raises the question of what united X's essence and existence. We cannot go to infinity, so the first cause of this union must be something in which essence and existence are numerically identical to each other, self-same. Again they are one, showcasing an aspect of divine simplicity. And that is God.

God then is "being itself subsisting," as St. Thomas expresses it.

3. Now that we have analyzed the consequences of the union of (potentiality + existence) and of (actuality + existence) in creatures, what remains is to see what the union of (potency + act) in them reveals about God.

As before, this union is artificial, contingent, and must be caused by something in which potency and act are entirely one. It does not make sense to say that whatever God is or is doing (act), He also can be (potency). But the reverse is quite meaningful: everything that God can be, He already is. And this signifies simply that God has no potentiality at all. Whatever God can extend to or do or enjoy, He already is in full possession of.

The conclusion is that God is pure act unmixed with any potency.

We have seen from argument 1) that in God, everything possible is potential. Argument 3) demonstrates further that in God, everything potential is actual. Hence, whatever is possible is actual in God. Therefore, all possible, and therefore all actually created, things pre-exist in God somehow as in their source of being, essence, and everything else.

Note that this argument does not preclude pantheism. Perhaps we are part of God, and all possible worlds are actual as constituent parts of God, especially if we argue that in God, the concrete and the abstract are self-same. More plausibly, however, creatures pre-exist in God as ideas in His mind, though this precise formulation may need a separate argument to be established. God is concrete as a self to be known as the Son, abstract as the thought knowing it as the Holy Spirit, which come together in a self-aware mind as the Father.

The identity of the abstract and concrete may be understood as that "2 + 2 = 4" is both an ideal proposition contemplated by God and a real component of the structure of the divine mind.

4. The argument from the contingency of the universe as a whole leads to a different conclusion. The question now is: Why is there something rather than nothing?

At first glance, the question seems befuddling. Why should there be nothing rather than what we have around us? Why privilege either "nothing" or "something"? Why cannot this world be everything that has ever been and will be?

On the one hand, we humans privilege nothing readily. We apparently come from nothing and go into nothing. In between we live for a little bit, always in danger, such that if we do not struggle with all our might, the nothing will arrive even quicker. All living things are born, thereby beginning to exist, and die, thereby ceasing to exist. But the inference from this human experience to the universe as a whole need not be taken.

Moreover, "something" is also privileged. The moment we are born, we are surrounded with stuff to use, enjoy, and manipulate. Disembodied existence, while not inconceivable, is not part of our human experience, though it may ultimately be natural in "heaven." But "nothingness" is inconceivable; one can't close his eyes and picture nothingness. However, that nothingness is inconceivable does not mean that it is impossible.

Let possible world Empty be defined as follows: ∀(x I can think of) [x does not exist in Empty]. Then

(1) Nothing = ∃[Empty]. We are dealing with "universes," uni = "one"; so, any possible world is a maximally consistent state of affairs. As a result, Empty swallows up every other reality; so, it is not necessary to say "there exists only Empty."

Let our actual world be called Terra. "Terra" is the name of the universe we live in, not of planet Earth. Then

(2) Something = ∃[Terra]. Neither is privileged, but just as before, (2) is only contingently true and demands an explanation.

Terra either has existed forever or was created. In either case, a physical cause of Terra is precluded from consideration, because it is situated before the effect. In the first case, infinite past cannot have a prior cause; and in the second case, time, too, began along with Terra, and it is meaningless to ask what happened "before" Terra began.

Since we are interested in the origin of the universe, neither teleological nor Aristotelian causation is applicable, either.

The cause of Terra joined the essence of Terra with existence by creating it. As a result, (2)'s being true has a "cause," and Terra's existing has a "ground" of its existence. This ground is called God. We have already seen the mode of causality of the first two grades: physical and teleological. An eternal grounding cause is the effecting of the 3rd grade, of goodness. Terra was united with its existence not at any moment in time but as a whole in eternity which "covers" merely everlasting existence (that we allowed for the sake of argument).

This is only half the task. Now we ask: What is this God? It cannot be another real thing, for then it, too, would stand in need of its own ground. It must then be "beyond" being. We conclude that God is not a thing at all but a kind of force, a primal principle that permeates all, that creates this world, so that its inhabitants might enjoy life or try to. That is what we mean when we say "God." God is not a thing but Creator of things. We may call it by the less ambitious and less potentially objectionable name, "creativity," or by the more ambitious one, "goodness," to the extent that one is inclined to consider Terra to be on the whole good and beautiful. But nothing is not a thing, either. So, in the beginning (of our story), we postulate nothing whatsoever (other than the 2nd-level God). It is a kind of clean slate, in which whatever is created (by goodness) can be made into a top-notch project or performance from ground up, with no need for backward compatibility.

Again, if goodness reigned, then in the beginning, there could not be anything, because only goodness creates good things, and nothing can exist whose existence goodness has not authorized. The choice goodness faced was: 2nd-level God + Empty or God + Terra.

To simplify: our options are: (a) goodness + nothing in the beginning and (b) a good thing, i.e., the world, in the beginning. Goodness implies "nothing," and "nothing" implies goodness; and now we see that their combination, i.e., (a), is also implied.

Note the difference between the last two arguments. The first establishes the identity of God's essence and existence. This is possible, because the essence of our electron can be fully comprehended. But it does not establish God's goodness, because there is no reason to hold that it is a "good thing" overall that a particular electron exists.

The second establishes God's goodness, because it is evident to any reasonably sane man that the universe as a whole is a very good thing. At the same time, it cannot prove the identity of the divine essence and His existence, because the universe as a whole is too big for me, not the least because I am part of it, and I cannot know myself fully, since in me the subject knowing is forever distinct from the object known. I cannot know the essence of the created universe. But I see that there may have been in its stead nothing at all.

These proofs relied on what I think is an uncontroversial principle that every contingent thing, including an actually imperishable one, must have a cause or perhaps "sufficient reason" which itself is necessary. We have by uniting in God what is diverse in creatures in the end demonstrated God's maximal creative power, an aspect of His simplicity, His pure actuality, that He is the archetype of all finite things, and His goodness.

Three Teleological Arguments for God’s Existence

Two arguments below will be deductive, and they come straight from my book. The third argument will be inductive, and I will show that it is inconclusive.

As per my methodology, the existence of God is proved by discovering, one adequate and unique argument after another, God's attributes or the meaning of the term "God." Moreover, unless God is shown to differ from creatures substantially, we gain nothing, since this God might as well be considered to be part of the universe.

1. Why does our universe obey laws rather than exhibit prime matter style chaos? "Laws of nature" are of course abstractions made by humans; nevertheless, the obvious orderliness of the world may point to something. This is an intuitive argument to the effect that at the beginning of every human project, there are raw materials and human labor that transforms them into something useful, virtuous, or pleasant. Similarly, it stands to reason that in the beginning of the universe, there was chaos which was later on ordered. The pure potency of prime matter is an ideal building block, because one is not constrained by any pre-existing form in shaping prime matter into whatever he desires. It grants absolute freedom to the maker to fashion out of such matter anything he likes.

Why do all things obey laws? Another argument that answers the question "Why is there something rather than nothing?" reveals that the universe was created out of nothing. What informed the universe with laws? If object A gave the law to matter, then if A itself is law-bound, then the problem remains. "What ordered A?" we are liable to ask. We cannot go to infinity; hence, the ultimate first cause of the order of the universe itself obeys no laws at all. But there are only two sorts of things that obey no laws at all: one is pure chaos, and the other is absolutely simple; pure potency and pure act. But the chaos of the former does not generate order. We must acknowledge this simple thing that is free to such a perfect degree to be the cause of order of the universe and to be God.

This argument proves deductively that the cause of the universe, whatever it is, is not restricted in its operation by any intricacies of its own nature. There are no "laws of the divine nature" (as there are laws of the nature of atoms, cats, and humans) that are prior to God which determine, condition, and thereby limit His functioning.

2. Now the inductive argument from the same. William Dembski has developed the notion of specified complexity (SC) which, when applied to physical mechanical systems (and in particular to biological structures, such as molecular robots within cells), permits and even makes inevitable a rational inference to intelligent design.

It may be possible to ascribe SC to the universe as a whole: not to any self-contained arrangement of material parts within it, but to its natural laws. I include the laws studied by both natural and social sciences, both, say, physics and economics.

There are then two questions. (1) Can we adopt the premise that the universe exhibits specified complexity? And (2) given that premise, can we conclude that if the universe was created, then whatever created it must be an intelligent thing?

One difference is that ID in biology studies "grace" which mingles with works of nature, such as perhaps evolution. But the design argument for God's existence deals not with post-creation grace that perfects nature but with the original divine act of creation of nature itself.

The second difference is that specified complexity for Dembski regards clever and sophisticated structure of working machines, be they tractors or bacterial flagella, i.e., complexity of something concrete. The SC of natural laws is abstract complexity, such as the complexity of the axiomatic-deductive math that models natural laws.

Despite these differences, I think the answer to (1) is yes.

However, the positive answer to (2) does not follow. Design inference in biology depends on the limited amount of computational resources in nature. And earth, despite the considerable length of its history, is certainly sufficiently finite.

With the universe, we cannot be sure of that. For all we know, there may be a googolplex (though not an infinitude) of other worlds, randomly generated, so that, although the vast majority are chaotic, ours just happened to be lucky to be ordered and intelligible.

The previous deductive argument cannot be ruined in this manner. Whatever X generated our world, as well as all the other ordered worlds out of the googolplex of all attempts either obeys its own laws or does not. If X is meaninglessly chaotic, then it cannot produce order in its effect. At the very least, X must be precisely tuned to reliably give birth to universes. If X is law-bound and rational, then the question of what made it so remains. The conclusion as before is that the first cause is efficiently free.

As a result, the deductive argument succeeds, and the inductive argument fails, at giving us a slice of God.

3. This argument may be called the problem of particularity: why is the world this and not something else? All chaotic worlds are identical to each other, all equally boring; but each orderly world is uniquely interesting, and again there is an infinitude of possible ordered worlds, so they cannot all exist. How did this particular world manage to obtain its highly peculiar reality out of an infinite number of its possible brethren?

I refer you to my book for a full explication of the consequences of this strange situation.

Divine Simplicity vs. Unity

We have seen that on the 1st level, God is materially simple.

On the 2nd level, it is better to speak of divine unity rather than simplicity. For example, a man is generally one spirit and enjoys the unity of experience despite being spectacularly complex in his body. Simplicity and unity then are different notions. God enjoys both "bodily" simplicity and unparalleled spiritual unity.

Thus, God exhibits no schizophrenic symptoms. He is not divided against Himself in any way. There are no inner contradictions within God. He does not experience cognitive dissonance; He does not have to reconcile his sensitive and intellectual appetites; He would not worship Satan for political power. Humans are conflicted in multiple ways; not God, however. His spirit showcases perfect and single-minded integrity.

Three Ways of Loving God

1. It is a traditional Christian trope that man's happiness is found in knowing God. But when put this way, God plays the role essentially of a consumer good, say, a book which is fun to read and study. When one loves God thus, he loves Him less than himself.

In other words, my own pleasure is the end; the knowledge to be learned is the pleasure-giving object; God and the vision of Him are a means to the acquisition of this knowledge. The means are inferior to the end and are treated accordingly.

This kind of love is impossible without grace, since we are aware of the promise of our beatitude via spiritual and intellectual union with God by faith alone. We don't know what God is in His essence, but we look forward to finding out and therefore love God as a good even in this life. In the state of glory, God will seem the most valuable thing of all.

2. But God -- and Jesus in particular -- is also a friend. On the one hand, it is inevitable that one loves himself more than any neighbor, since one is united with himself more tightly than with any other human or angel. (Loving neighbor as oneself pertains to the perfection of charity. St. Thomas, too, comments that it's not a precept of charity that "a man must love his neighbor equally as himself, but in like manner as himself." (ST, II-II, 44, 7))

On the other hand, God is perfect, and this perfection is actually infinite. Humans are by nature (and especially when strengthened in the state of glory, to be discussed later) potentially infinite. Hence God's holiness and happiness are something forever for man to aspire to. Man then relates to God as his present self relates to endless future improvement. It is clear that in this case, one loves God as intensely as himself.

Again, without grace, one cannot be friends with God, because this perpetual improvement is not anticipated in mere natural state. One must believe in and hope for everlasting life and our Lord's provident kingship over the communion of saints.

3. Finally, God on the 3rd level is absolute goodness, one's Creator and Maker, and the source of everything good including one's nature, existence, happiness, grace, and glory.

Though a man is united with himself in many various ways, this adhesion is effected by love which is the divine light itself infused into him. But when X is glued to a numerically distinct Y however strongly, the glue is closer to both X and Y than X and Y are to each other. Thus, God is closer to a man than even the man to his own essence or life or enjoyment.

It therefore befits man to love God more than himself as the ultimate benefactor.

An unregenerated person will tend to think in his philosophical moments that the evil in the world outweighs and trumps the good, because it will appear to him that everything dies. Our bodies suffer and decay; our creations malfunction and break. Even the human race as a whole seems to be in a highly precarious position; and an ungodly man can have no illusions of hope whatever for himself personally. As a result, an atheist must needs be a natural pessimist for whom existence is on the whole evil. Hence, he cannot make the inference that God is good or goodness, and so will not love Him in the 3rd way, either.

Proof of God’s Material Simplicity

I have shown that God is physically omnipresent at every point in space, wholly present in all such points, and cannot be pushed out of them. Thus, God is unmoved and immovable.

In addition, God can be shown to be immense and have the kinetic energy of zero.

That God is materially simple on His 1st level follows. If God were composed of several material parts, then each point in space would have to be occupied by all of these parts at once. And this is impossible, since no two physical objects can be in one and the same location at the same time. Hence God's material cause, "what it is made of," is simple.

This answers the question, "Why is there motion?" God simplicity is revealed by tracing the implications of spatial motion. There are at least two other pregnant questions, "Why is the motion predictable and orderly rather than chaotic?" and "Why do things move in a straight line rather than any other rational trajectory, say, an ellipse or spiral?"

Answering the second question in the manner I do in my book proves God's absolute freedom. God has no 1st-level efficient cause, "how it works."

Answering the third question demonstrates that God has the power of rational choice.

I do not make it clear in my book that God's simplicity requires a separate argument to demonstrate, so I'm supplying it in this post.

Perfections of the Divine Levels

The perfection of the 1st level lies in God's simplicity or lack of composition and in freedom. Freedom means absence of constraints imposed on one by anything other than one's own nature. Further, God is unified and integrated so tightly that He is a seamless simple being, whose existence is His essence. God is "being itself subsisting"; His essence is not activated by existence but is being itself. This means that God's nature can in no wise be pried away or disentangled from His existence, and therefore, God is incapable of corrupting or dying. As a result, God is not a conjunction of some piece A and piece B united and interacting according to natural laws that are prior to God and which God obeys.

The perfection of the 2nd level lies (1) in Trinitarian completeness of God, (2) in His nobility and excellence, and (3) in perfect and infinite happiness.

The perfection of the 3rd level is in self-diffusion of goodness and in world without end.

When we say that the Father, Son, and Holy Spirit are good, we mean it in the way similar to when we say that a human body is animate, with the "levels" increased by 1. It's a metaphor, for we do not see the soul with the corporeal eyes; nor understand goodness with our intellect. But humans are not spiritual or animate machines; they are machine-like spirits. Thus also God is not a good spirit but spiritual goodness.

We Were Always Meant to Be

God did not "have to" create the world, because this term applies to physical causation which did not operate; nor did he "want to" create it, because it falsely supposes teleological causation. The world was not caused in either of these two ways. It was caused through the diffusion of divine goodness into being. In other words, these statements are true only in the sense of indicating the correct causal level. It's true that God did not have to create, but only because creation did not occur through physical causation; He did not want to create, because the it did not occur through teleological causation.

For example, the dismissal of teleology should immediately be seen to be justified when we wonder what moved, as in gave an incentive to, the first mover to thrust Himself into the action of creating. Is it not a given that God is perfectly happy? Then what was allegedly missing in His life that He needed to remedy this void in His heart by creating us? Why did God not continue to live free from care and enjoy his eternal life 100% quite without a distraction as bothersome and irritating as this world?

This does not entail that the world is necessary. For one, on the 3rd level, all such terms are meaningless. It is senseless to ask what God was doing prior to creation and what at some particular moment in time inclined Him to command that let there be light.

The notion of time does not apply to 3rd-level goodness, either, though the triune 2nd-level God is eternal, as in combining in Himself the unified simple perfection of past, present, future, and timelessness. As I argue regarding the "awakenings" of the persons of the Trinity, the Father never lacked His ad extra will and power, as per how Goodness arranged it. The Father's life had no momentous events in it like the Incarnation was for the Son. The intellects of all three persons were fully awake from the beginning, but the Father is logically first, since His natural knowledge precedes the Holy Spirit's middle knowledge and the Son's free knowledge in the order of employment during the act of creation.

The world is contingent, because the Son chose of His own free will wisely as "logos" or reason which possible and then potential world pleased Him the most, having considered the data provided by both the natural and then middle knowledge.

As a corollary, the Son's freedom to choose a world to actualize entailed His freedom not to choose any world at all and so abstain from creating.

Nevertheless, we were always in eternity meant to be. Goodness was going to create the world at the "outset."

God = Goodness, 4

A man is wise to the extent that he grasps the overall divine design of the created world. In his wisdom, he judges the world to be a good thing, starting from the most general fact that everything that exists is good (and good to the extent that it exists, i.e., according to the plenitude of its essence) and ending with the minutia of divine providence and his own personal salvation. From these and with the help of supporting arguments he concludes that God is Goodness itself that is beyond being: not being but Creator of being.

He arrives at the triplist metaphysics: the 1st level of matter and physical causality, the 2nd of spirit and teleology, and 3rd of divine goodness and its self-diffusion.

The last of these, goodness, belongs only to God. This qualitative superiority is the pith of the difference between God and creatures.

As he learns about the 2nd-level of God which is the Father-Son-Holy Spirit, he further admires this 3rd-level essential goodness of God even apart from the created world by meditating on the perfection (as omniscience, etc.) of God's 2nd-level being.

Why Recite the Articles of Faith?

In Chapter 6, Landsburg makes a number of claims, some of them false, and others rather good.

He begins by describing his Orthodox Jewish friend Misha proclaiming every day that "I believe with perfect faith in the coming of the Messiah, and though he may tarry, nevertheless I believe." Landsburg objects in reply: "I believe with perfect faith that the square root of two is an irrational number, but I have never felt an ongoing need to announce that conviction to the Universe. That's why I suspect that Misha is a liar." The reason is that Misha must be brainwashing himself: "the 'beliefs' I echo are those I might want to believe, or those I'm trying to talk myself into, or those that I'm trying on for size. But when I pass the threshold to actual belief, I stop reviewing the matter." (55-6)

But this confuses reason and faith as sources of belief. Thus, I believe that Christ is Lord with "perfect" faith, while Landsburg believes that "the square root of two is an irrational number" not with perfect faith but with perfect reason.

What is faith? It's an assent of the intellect to the revealed knowledge of God. Specifically, "to faith those things in themselves belong, the sight of which we shall enjoy in eternal life, and by which we are brought to eternal life." (ST, II-II, 1, 8) There are secret things that are of God that humans cannot discover by reason alone but that can only be known through divine revelation. Thus, the Bible relates: "Jesus spoke to them only in parables, to fulfill what had been said through the prophet: 'I will open my mouth in parables, I will announce what has lain hidden from the foundation [of the world].'" (Mt 13:34-35) Of course, Christianity itself is not an esoteric religion at all; all its gems are hidden in plain sight.

St. Thomas writes that faith stands midway between science and opinion. This becomes clear if we compare the relative strengths of the influences that impel a person to come to believe. A scientific demonstration of a conclusion will move the mind to accept the conclusion as true inexorably. Scientific evidence is seen either by sensation or reflection and hence has intrinsic power to convince. For example, seeing chlorine produced from salt is sufficient to persuade anybody of the correctness of the chemical reaction

2NaCl + 2H2O → Cl2 + H2 + 2NaOH.

On the other hand, faith requires an act of choice to give in to God-given disposition to believe and to accept the unseen knowledge revealed to one by God -- knowledge that cannot be obtained by scientific investigation. One can go either way, but when the assent is given, the falsity of the propositions opposite to those that are the object of faith is not in doubt, precisely as is the case with scientific demonstrations.

By contrast, opinion is changeable and readily accepts the possibility of the opposite and so can at any time be swayed by new arguments: "the intellect assents to something, not through being sufficiently moved to this assent by its proper object, but through an act of choice, whereby it turns voluntarily to one side rather than to the other: and if this be accompanied by doubt or fear of the opposite side, there will be opinion, while, if there be certainty and no fear of the other side, there will be faith." (ST, II-II, 1, 4)

Here is the clincher: this choice must be made anew every day, and therefore the confession of faith must be recited every day as a sign of one's preference.

I find no need to keep declaring that God exists, either; I know it in the same way in which Landsburg knows the properties of the square root of two. I do not "announce to the Universe" that "there is a God, and He is simple, eternal, perfectly happy, all-knowing," and so on. I already have excellent reasons for believing all this, having proved it to my satisfaction through philosophy. I may still invoke these facts in my prayer, anyway, insofar as "things which can be proved by demonstration are reckoned among the articles of faith, not because they are believed simply by all, but because they are a necessary presupposition to matters of faith, so that those who do not known them by demonstration must know them first of all by faith." (ST, II-II, 1, 5, reply 3) Note, however, that the Nicene creed is only about faith-based knowledge, e.g., "We believe in... the Father, the Almighty, Maker of all that is, seen and unseen. We believe in one Lord, Jesus Christ, the only Son of God..." That God is a Trinity is a revealed truth.

Again, "the existence of God and other like truths about God, which can be known by natural reason, are not articles of faith, but are preambles to the articles; for faith presupposes natural knowledge, even as grace presupposes nature, and perfection supposes something that can be perfected," says St. Thomas (ST, I, 2, 2, reply 1). This natural foundation for faith requires perfect intellectual consistency and coherence of natural theology. Any flaw in our metaphysics, concept of God, meaning of life, and so on can cause the entire structure of nature + grace to collapse. An intelligent person already suspicious of faith who perceives mistakes in our reasoning is unlikely to believe.

The choice to believe is neither irrational nor a type of violent self-brainwashing. It is aided from below by lack of contradictions in the purely rational conception of God and related matters, by how well the faith builds on natural knowledge, and by personal virtue that does not cloud the intellect through sin and hypocrisy; and from above by divine grace which creates a lyrical enchantment with the articles of faith. Faith and science are similar in the sense that assenting to true beliefs and rejecting false beliefs, as a rule, leads to happiness, while the opposite actions lead to misery.

Now science is amenable to new evidence. But then so is faith. Like science, faith improves with time and always has, both "in the number of articles believed explicitly, since to those who lived in later times some were known explicitly which were not known explicitly by those who lived before them" (ST, II-II, 1, 7); and in our understanding of them.

Finally, faith is not a purely speculative subject but is also a master plan of the life-long project of saving oneself, of earning heaven. Reciting the confession is a way to re-affirm one's commitment against every temptation and evil. We can see that Misha, though a Jew and not a Christian, is acting 100% reasonably and honestly.

Intellect of God; the Multiverse

Mises talked about the "logical structure of the human mind." The human thinking process is rule-bound.

So is God's, except in Him, there prevails an identity between the intellect / its structure, God's thought, the thing understood, and His act of understanding. Somehow the entire structure of God's mind is equivalent to a thought that comprehends this mind.

What does God know ad intra, in Himself?

First, all possibilities of finite existence.

Second, necessary truths like axioms and theorems of logic and mathematics. It may be asked, if truth is correspondence of thought to reality, then to what does the proposition "2 + 2 = 4" correspond? It corresponds not to "reality" as such but to a fundamental limitation on reality; not to what reality is but to what reality must necessarily be. No world in which 2 + 2 = 5 is possible; nor is God the Son irrational in this sense.

Thus, logic and math are neither in space nor in time and are the same across possible worlds.

Geometry is not in time but in space and therefore different across possible worlds; even in this world there are different geometries.

Certain propositions, such as "Christ will be born," are not in space but their truth values depend upon the moment in time at which they are uttered.

Laws of economics are neither in space nor in time but depend on human nature. Since God knows that humans are possible, He likewise knows all that can be predicated of them.

God is free to create a world in which 2 + 2 = 5, but limited in power by math; God is powerful enough to create a world in which saints went to hell, but His goodness does not allow that.

Just as a cat would know all the ways in which a man is like a cat (say, in having a stomach) but be ignorant of how a man exceeds a cat in perfection, so we do not know what God is (and thereby knows) that is above man by natural reason.

We do know a few things from special revelation, either Biblical or private, such as the Trinity;

we can speculate on the conditions of glorified life;

we can extend dualism into triplism by asserting that God's goodness is a third kind of substance beyond both matter and spirit;

we can admire the majesty of divine providence and the middle knowledge of the Holy Spirit;

we can stress the supreme importance of Christian charity and the many unions to be achieved by man;

we can marvel at the perfection of the Son's both utilitarian governance through disinterested benevolence and His enormous personal love for each human being.

However, the above list hardly exhausts God. We might even venture to propose that God is a universal set of all truths which miraculously comes alive as self-aware mind. Since the universal set is for humans a self-contradictory notion (would this set be a member of itself?), this may be the reason why God is incomprehensible. God instantiates in His own nature what we humans cannot for the life of us countenance.

If the universal set could be grasped, then one would be God. That it's impossible suggests the impossibility of humans reaching divine status.

The hypothesis in physics of the "multiverse," far from being atheistic, is in fact a backhanded concession that God exists. The multiverse itself as an infinite collection of actual worlds is a crude and distorted idea of God. I argued that God knows possible worlds, but these worlds, except our own, do not exist. Moreover, ideal things, such as the set of all natural numbers, can be infinite in number; actual things, such as the number of atoms in the universe, are always finite. The "multiverse" idea ignores this elementary distinction.

The multiverse therefore is a bizarre and primitive perversion of God the Father and a lamentably pantheistic view at that.

Whether God Knows Evil Things?

Evil is a privation of perfection that ought to be there. Consider the idea of a perfect knife. It's extra sharp and easily sharpened, durable, comfortable, well-balanced, weighs just the right amount, will cut anything, and so on. Suppose now that I have an imperfect knife. We can say: the knife is at 65% of maximum possible goodness. I know the good by seeing it by vision, and I know the knife's evil 35% through its goodness, by understanding intellectually how or in what ways precisely it falls short of perfection.

Similarly, a perfect man would presumably be Jesus. Human saints approach but never reach moral perfection. Most people have both good and evil qualities about them. Again, however, evil is a privation, a lack of fitting virtue or wisdom. I know the actual evil by "subtracting" the actual good from the ideal perfection.

This, too, is how God knows evil things: by considering to what extent their good is below perfect.

Main Difference Between Angels, Humans, and Animals

Angels lead contemplative lives but not active lives.

Animals have active lives but do not contemplate. (As a result, their souls are corruptible unless explicitly preserved in being after death by an act of God.)

And humans can enjoy both contemplative and active lives, as they themselves prefer.

Awakenings of Persons of the Trinity

All of the Father's faculties were fully mobilized before His creative act.

Moreover, the intellects of the Holy Spirit and the Son were uplifted before creation.

Regarding the Holy Spirit, His power was awakened immediately after creation; and His will, just before the giving of the first grace to the angels.

Regarding the Son, His power was uplifted at His conception during the Incarnation; and His will, upon His death on the cross.

Trinity: Ad Intra and Ad Extra

God's intellect, will, and power are each divided into 3 kinds for the Father, Son, and Holy Spirit.

First, ad intra.

God is an infinite mind that thinks itself into existence and in so doing becomes self-aware.

The Father is intellect, the subject that knows, which is a union of everything real and ideal. The Holy Spirit is thought, self-knowledge, intelligible species, a simple and comprehensive act of full self-understanding, which is ideal. Hence "the Spirit scrutinizes everything, even the depths of God" (1 Cor 2:10), as a thought penetrates to the essence of a thing being examined. The Son is the object known, which is real.

St. Thomas argues that "in God, intellect, and the object understood, and the intelligible species, and His act of understanding are entirely one and the same. Hence when God is said to be understanding, no kind of multiplicity is attached to His substance." (ST, I, 14, 4)

The Father wishes to grasp His own essence. The Holy Spirit's will is Love and Gift. The Father loves the Son by giving Him being / existence, and gives to Him the gift of perfection of essence and full access to and comprehension of the Father. The Son in His turn loves the Father by enjoying the Father's gift perfectly and infinitely, and gives to Him the gift of perfect fealty and justice to His reality. The Son's will consists in self-love, specifically to seek, obtain, and enjoy perfect and unconditional happiness.

The Father's power is to beget the Son, to self-actualize or to realize Himself, to attain perfect cognition of Himself. The Holy Spirit's power is to comprehend the Father, to envelop Him in thought. The Son's power is to be begotten. The Son has no inner contradictions or opposing forces within Him. Nor is the Son in any way composite at all but is 100% simple. He has His being by His very nature, and it is in this supreme integrity that His power to "be what He is" and endure forever consists.

Of course, the power is God identical to its exercise within His act of self-understanding.

Second, ad extra.

God is Creator, Sanctifier, and Redeemer.

The Father possesses the natural knowledge of all possible finite worlds. The Holy Spirit possesses the middle knowledge of the potential worlds and the counterfactuals of freedom. For this reason, it is the Holy Spirit who is able to "speak through the prophets," as per the creed. The Son possesses the free knowledge of the actual world. For this reason, it is "through Him" that the world was made; i.e., the Son decided by and for Himself which world was the best possible one and was to be created.

The Father's will is to manifest His goodness. The Father does not Himself seek happiness; He wills that creatures-who-seek-happiness exist. The Holy Spirit's will is to unite all rational creatures into one communion of angels and saints through charity. The Son's will is personal love for each individual. I have already proposed that the Holy Spirit ought rightly to be considered the 2nd person of the Trinity, and the Son, the 3rd. I mentioned an objection to this in regard to the scope of each person's mission to the created world. But now we can see how this objection can be answered: the Father is concerned with the entire universe as before; the Holy Spirit, while giving unique graces to individuals, is concerned with the union of mankind; and the Son, while uniting the human race to Godhead, is concerned with the salvation of each individual human being.

The Father's power is to create ex nihilo; the Holy Spirit's power is to bestow grace; and the Son's power is to rule the created world with perfect and abiding competence for all eternity.

Production in Paradise: Objections

1. In one account of a near-death experience, the person saw a group of folks with Zeus-like physiques who were playing some kind of game which involved a ball. Where did this ball come from? If humans in paradise acquire a power to simply have things wished for magically appear, then they become equal to the Father who can create ex nihilo. This is impossible; besides, such absolute power would corrupt everyone (but the Father).

(St. Thomas' argument proves this last proposition decisively: "God's power is His goodness: hence He cannot use His power otherwise than well. But it is not so with men. Consequently it is not enough for man's happiness, that he become like God in power, unless he become like Him in goodness also." (ST, II-I, 2, 4, reply 1) But the latter is not possible. Hence, neither is the former, and not even close.)

2. Could those players have asked the Father to create a ball for them? This, too, is grotesque, because humans already have their own power to control the material world. This life is partly about subduing the earth and learning to tame wild nature for our own benefit. The idea that such a major aspect of human existence as mind over matter would just disappear so completely in paradise is difficult to take seriously.

Even worse, we would be dependent on the Father for everything. We'd have to beg Him to give us toothbrushes. But humans are noble and self-sufficient creatures. It is completely unbecoming for us to grovel before God for basketballs.

3. Another possibility is that we won't need any goods at all in paradise. Perhaps life will consist of endless carousing: parties, sex, consuming those nectar and ambrosia (this is really the only way to get food without harming the plants). But I think this would become boring quickly. Everlasting life cannot consist of an endless stream of identical experiences.

4. Finally, perhaps there is no paradise; only heaven, where there is nothing but the Thomistic "contemplation of God seen in His essence." This, however, is a most perverse opinion, because humans are not angels, and they differ from angels precisely in having (and needing) an active life. As such, humans fill a unique niche in the hierarchy of being and essence, and help complete that hierarchy together with the angels.

Nature and Nature’s God

In response to my post, a person on Facebook advanced the thesis that "God does not create anything evil." But God the Father's mission is now finished. It was completed upon creating nature. He no longer creates anything. The world creates or advances itself, due allowance being made for intelligent design and grace by the Holy Spirit.

And nature is for various reasons imperfect, even obscene. It's still merciless, but it can be cruel, else there would not be birth defects or sickness or famines.

I replied therefore with a line from Seinfeld: "Mother nature is a mad scientist!"

Perhaps this is yet another way to understand the necessity of the missions of the Holy Spirit and the Son: to compensate for the obvious incongruity between the ruthlessness of nature and its own scandalously wounded and perverse state.

It is a visible injustice for God to subject us to judgment by something so evidently corrupt and therefore unqualified to be an authority as the nature of the world.

This is also why worshiping material nature, such as by holding that physical phenomena are in the care of spirits, is an unfortunate mistake the ancients sometimes made: in fact, nature is grim and implacable and will not be swayed by either prayers or curses.

Whether God Is a “Hard Man”?

Jesus tells a fascinating (and terrifying) "parable of the talents" which concludes as follows:

Then the one who had received the one talent came forward and said,

"Master, I knew you were a demanding person, harvesting where you did not plant and gathering where you did not scatter; so out of fear I went off and buried your talent in the ground. Here it is back."

His master said to him in reply,

"You wicked, lazy servant! So you knew that I harvest where I did not plant and gather where I did not scatter? Should you not then have put my money in the bank so that I could have got it back with interest on my return?

"Now then! Take the talent from him and give it to the one with ten. For to everyone who has, more will be given and he will grow rich; but from the one who has not, even what he has will be taken away.

"And throw this useless servant into the darkness outside, where there will be wailing and grinding of teeth." (Mt 25:24-30)

One striking feature is how well this confirms the essence of the human condition: perpetual improvement in whatever each man is interested in, his soul included. This life requires one, as a rule, to strive for happiness and succeed. Mises puts it this way:

As long as a man lives, he cannot help obeying the cardinal impulse, the elan vital. It is man's innate nature that he seeks to preserve and to strengthen his life, that he is discontented and aims at removing uneasiness, that he is in search of what may be called happiness.

In every living being there works an inexplicable and nonanalyzable Id. This Id is the impulsion of all impulses, the force that drives man into life and action, the original and ineradicable craving for a fuller and happier existence. It works as long as man lives and stops only with the extinction of life. (HA, 882)

I conclude my book with asking, "what is the universe for if not a process of its eternal self-improvement?"

But here I want to focus on another aspect of the parable, which is God agreeing that He "harvests where He did not plant and gathers where He did not scatter."

This much is obvious, given the existence of nature and its secondary causes which interpose between the Father and His creatures. New humans themselves appear on earth through perfectly natural human reproduction and its genetic lottery. God does not determine the make-up of one's body; nature does. God then must take humans as He finds them, with all the (random) defects of their nature, bodies, and -- because of the intimate union of the body and soul -- their spirits / personalities, as well.

So then, does God get what He can from nature and impatiently waves aside the failures? Is He a cold-blooded perfect utilitarian who ushers the successful into heaven and unceremoniously throws the human refuse that proves itself worthless into hell as irrelevant aborted "clumps of cells"? Is life survival of the saintliest?

Earlier I pointed out how unforgiving nature is, and how the Father reflects (or rather causes) this condition of our lives.

In an important book on the vitamins-as-treatment medical paradigm, Abram Hoffer et al. write:

[Bill Walsh's] experiences led him to compare mineral levels in the hair of twenty-four pairs of brothers. In each case, one brother was a well-behaved member of society, while the other was a "boy from hell."

The results were amazing. The hair analyses showed that well-behaved males had normal mineral levels, but the imprisoned delinquents all showed one of two abnormal patterns.

"Boys from hell" had either very high copper and very low zinc, sodium, and potassium levels in their hair or very low zinc and copper and very high sodium and potassium.

In addition, the delinquents also had lead and cadmium levels that were three times greater than those of their well-behaved siblings. (Niacin: The Real Story, Ch. 8)

If the behavior of these boys was influenced (though not caused) by their bodily chemistry, such as poisoning by heavy metals, it seems improper to condemn the boys from hell to hell for moral flaws that flowed from something as obviously irrelevant to the fate of their immortal souls as unusual mineral ratios in their systems. Can God really be so callous as to condemn to eternal horror people whom fully to cure physically and improve morally would take nothing more difficult than prescribing a cheap nutritional supplement?

Are we toys whom God casually tosses aside when they no longer amuse Him? It seems unbecoming of the goodness of God to give up on us so easily.

And that's precisely why the history of the world from the point of view of God is incomplete without the other 2 persons of the divine Trinity, the Holy Spirit and the Son.

We can go even further and affirm that without these two, literally no one would get to the Father, who wants absolute metaphysical and moral perfection from us. The human project would be a 100% failure without (1) grace and progress in charity and (2) forgiveness of sins.